22 research outputs found

    Hyperlogic: A System for Talking about Logics

    Get PDF
    Sentences about logic are often used to show that certain embedding expressions, including attitude verbs, conditionals, and epistemic modals, are hyperintensional. Yet it not clear how to regiment ā€œlogic talkā€ in the object language so that it can be compositionally embedded under such expressions. This paper does two things. First, it argues against a standard account of logic talk, viz., the impossible worlds semantics. It is shown that this semantics does not easily extend to a language with propositional quantifiers, which are necessary for regimenting some logic talk. Second, it develops an alternative framework based on logical expressivism, which explains logic talk using shifting conventions. When combined with the standard S5Ļ€+ semantics for propositional quantifiers, this framework results in a well-behaved system that does not face the problems of the impossible worlds semantics. It can also be naturally extended with hybrid operators to regiment a broader range of logic talk, e.g., claims about what laws hold according to other logics. The resulting system, called hyperlogic, is therefore a better framework for modeling logic talk than previous accounts

    Against Conventional Wisdom

    Get PDF
    Conventional wisdom has it that truth is always evaluated using our actual linguistic conventions, even when considering counterfactual scenarios in which different conventions are adopted. This principle has been invoked in a number of philosophical arguments, including Kripkeā€™s defense of the necessity of identity and Lewyā€™s objection to modal conventionalism. But it is false. It fails in the presence of what Einheuser (2006) calls c-monsters, or convention-shifting expressions (on analogy with Kaplanā€™s monsters, or context-shifting expressions). We show that c-monsters naturally arise in contexts, such as metalinguistic negotiations, where speakers entertain alternative conventions. We develop an expressivist theoryā€”inspired by Barker (2002) and MacFarlane (2016) on vague predications and Einheuser (2006) on counterconventionalsā€”to model these shifts in convention. Using this framework, we reassess the philosophical arguments that invoked the conventional wisdom

    What Can You Say? Measuring the Expressive Power of Languages

    Get PDF
    There are many different ways to talk about the world. Some ways of talking are more expressive than othersā€”that is, they enable us to say more things about the world. But what exactly does this mean? When is one language able to express more about the world than another? In my dissertation, I systematically investigate different ways of answering this question and develop a formal theory of expressive power, translation, and notational variance. In doing so, I show how these investigations help to clarify the role that expressive power plays within debates in metaphysics, logic, and the philosophy of language

    Counterpossibles

    Get PDF
    Philosophy Compass, EarlyView

    Logic talk

    Get PDF
    Sentences about logic are often used to show that certain embedding expressions are hyperintensional. Yet it is not clear how to regiment ā€œlogic talkā€ in the object language so that it can be compositionally embedded under such expressions. In this paper, I develop a formal system called hyperlogic that is designed to do just that. I provide a hyperintensional semantics for hyperlogic that doesnā€™t appeal to logically impossible worlds, as traditionally understood, but instead uses a shiftable parameter that determines the interpretation of the logical connectives. I argue this semantics compares favorably to the more common impossible worlds semantics, which faces difficulties interpreting propositionally quantified logic talk

    The Logic of Hyperlogic. Part B: Extensions and Restrictions

    Get PDF
    This is the second part of a two-part series on the logic of hyperlogic, a formal system for regimenting metalogical claims in the object language (even within embedded environments). Part A provided a minimal logic for hyperlogic that is sound and complete over the class of all models. In this part, we extend these completeness results to stronger logics that are sound and complete over restricted classes of models. We also investigate the logic of hyperlogic when the language is enriched with hyperintensional operators such as counterfactual conditionals and belief operators

    The Logic of Hyperlogic. Part A: Foundations

    Get PDF
    Hyperlogic is a hyperintensional system designed to regiment metalogical claims (e.g., "Intuitionistic logic is correct" or "The law of excluded middle holds") into the object language, including within embedded environments such as attitude reports and counterfactuals. This paper is the first of a two-part series exploring the logic of hyperlogic. This part presents a minimal logic of hyperlogic and proves its completeness. It consists of two interdefined axiomatic systems: one for classical consequence (truth preservation under a classical interpretation of the connectives) and one for "universal" consequence (truth preservation under any interpretation). The sequel to this paper explores stronger logics that are sound and complete over various restricted classes of models as well as languages with hyperintensional operators

    Verbal Disagreement and Semantic Plans

    Get PDF
    I develop an expressivist account of verbal disagreements as practical disagreements over how to use words rather than factual disagreements over what words actually mean. This account enjoys several advantages over others in the literature: it can be implemented in a neo-Stalnakerian possible worlds framework; it accounts for cases where speakers are undecided on how exactly to interpret an expression; it avoids appeals to fraught notions like subject matter, charitable interpretation, and joint-carving; and it naturally extends to an analysis of metalinguistic negotiations

    Does Chance Undermine Would?

    Get PDF
    Counterfactual skepticism holds that most ordinary counterfactuals are false. The main argument for this view appeals to a ā€˜chance undermines wouldā€™ principle: if Ļˆ would have some chance of not obtaining had Ļ† obtained, then Ļ† []ā€“\u3e Ļˆ is false. This principle seems to follow from two fairly weak principles, viz., that ā€˜chance ensures couldā€™ and that Ļ† []ā€“\u3e Ļˆ and Ļ† \u3c\u3eā€“\u3e Ļˆ clash. Despite their initial plausibility, I show that these principles are independently problematic: given some modest closure principles, they entail absurdities. Moreover, on the most promising strategy for saving these principles, they do not, in the relevant sense, entail the chance-undermines-would principle. Instead, they entail a principle that only supports counterfactual indeterminism, the view that most ordinary counterfactuals are chancy, i.e., not settled true. I demonstrate this by developing an indeterminist semantics that vindicates the clash and chance-ensures-could principles but not the chance-undermines-would principle. This view, I argue, offers a better account of our credal and linguistic judgments than counterfactual skepticism

    What Topic Continuity Problem?

    Get PDF
    A common objection to the very idea of conceptual engineering is the topic continuity problem: whenever one tries to ā€œreengineerā€ a concept, one only shifts attention away from one concept to another. Put diļ¬€erently, there is no such thing as conceptual revision: thereā€™s only conceptual replacement. Here, I show that topic continuity is compatible with conceptual replacement. Whether the topic is preserved in an act of conceptual replacement simply depends on what is being replaced (a conceptual tool or a conceptual role) and what the topic under discussion is. Thus, the topic continuity problem only arises from a failure to specify these two things
    corecore